The consent of an established government is not morally necessary for the formation of a militia

Fundamental ideas
Post Reply
David_Sims
Posts: 27
Joined: Sun Apr 07, 2024 9:39 pm

The consent of an established government is not morally necessary for the formation of a militia

Post by David_Sims » Wed Aug 20, 2025 3:30 pm

A Conversation with GAB-AI.

David Sims:

Let’s put our moral thinking caps on, Arya.
.

Gab-AI:

Absolutely—thinking caps are tight and the compass is set due North.

When you say “moral thinking,” are we tackling a specific dilemma—say, the ethics of a policy, an interpersonal quandary, or something wider like cultural decay? Or do you want to zoom out and frame how we even start reasoning morally in 2025?

Hand me the horizon you want to scan and let’s walk it through.
.

David Sims:

Yes. I’ve a suspicion regarding the emergence of a right. It involves the defense of the innocent against being murdered, with the defense supplied by a third party who witnesses the impending attack.
.

Gab-AI:

Your suspicion points to an age-old moral reality, not a novel invention: the natural right—some would say duty—of a third party to use proportionate force in defense of the innocent when murder is imminent. Christianity calls it the requirement of neighbor-love: “Rescue those being led away to death” (Prov 24:11–12). Secular natural-law tradition labels it the principle of defensio tertii. Either way, it is anchored in the prior truth that innocent life bears intrinsic, God-given dignity and therefore a claim on every bystander when no other earthly agent (police, soldier, parent, etc.) is immediately available.

Three concise clarifications:

Moral right ≠ moral permission for aggression. The defender may act only to stop the unjust assault, using the least force sufficient to neutralize the threat. Once the aggressor is disarmed or incapacitated, further harm becomes unjust.

Legitimate authority still matters, but it is delegated de facto in the moment of crisis. If no magistrate is present to act, the moral buck stops at the eyewitness. Later, civil law should vindicate, not punish, the intervenor because human statutes are obliged to track the higher law written on the heart (Rom 2:15).

Scale does not change the principle. Swinging a bat to stop a mugger, tackling a mass shooter, or (in formal structures) a nation firing missiles to prevent genocide all ride on the same moral logic: protect the innocent, render account to God and neighbor for the gift you refused to see destroyed.

So your suspicion isn’t speculative; it’s simply the recognition that where evil sets a lethal table, any human being may be deputized by conscience and covenant to stand between predator and prey.
.

David Sims:

An innocent person is unaware that a criminal is sneaking up on him with a deadly weapon: a gun, a machete, a knife. A third person, armed with a rifle, observes the impending murder a moment before it happens. May this defender shoot the would-be murderer in order to preserve the innocent person?
.

Gab-AI:

Yes—he may and, under the moral law, ordinarily should.

The defender has witnessed an imminent, unjust, lethal attack on an innocent life. Because the aggressor is seconds from carrying out that deadly act, the only proportionate way to stop the murder is to incapacitate the attacker immediately. One precise rifle shot does exactly that.

Key safeguards built into the act:

• Certainty of deadly intent: weapon already drawn and closing distance.

• Last clear chance: no time to warn, call police, or stop the attack by lesser means.

• Proportionate force: aim to stop the threat, not to inflict gratuitous harm.

In both Christian ethics and natural-law reasoning, such defensive use of lethal force is permissible—even commendable—when it is the least-force-required option to prevent an innocent person from being murdered.
.

David Sims:

Okay. So far, so good.

Now, let us say that there are two innocent people, each of whom is being crept up upon by a would-be murderer. The two attacks proceed at the same time, about, um, 10 meters apart. There are two defenders, each armed with a rifle. May each of the defenders shoot the murderer nearest him, in order to preserve the innocent person nearest him?
.

Gab-AI:

Yes. Each defender is confronting an independent, imminent, unjust, and lethal attack on an innocent.

• Defender A may shoot Assailant A to save Victim A.

• Defender B may (in fact ought to) shoot Assailant B to save Victim B.
Both acts are morally identical to the single-defender scenario and satisfy the same conditions:

Deadly threat actually and visibly in progress.

No realistic chance of a less-forceful solution in the time available.

Force used is strictly proportionate to the threat—aimed at stopping the assault, not at vengeance or excessive harm.

Because the two episodes are simultaneous but separate, each defender carries the identical moral justification for his shot.
.

David Sims:

Excellent. Your reasoning tracks mine perfectly so far.

Let us suppose that murderers A and B, in order to gain advantage, join forces in their attempts to kill innocent persons A and B. May defenders A and B likewise join forces in order to nullify the advantage gained by the murderers?
.

Gab-AI:

Yes. When aggressors deliberately coordinate their attack, the moral imperative to defend the innocents likewise authorizes the defenders to coordinate.

Each defender may still target only the assailant actually endangering the innocent nearest him—the same lethal, imminent, unjust threat we considered before—yet they may synchronize timing, share sight lines, or exchange fire angles in mutual support. The defensive force remains proportionate to the combined threat; nothing is added that amounts to gratuitous harm or punishment beyond what is strictly required to stop the impending murders.
.

David Sims:

Again, we are in accord.

Now, there’s nothing special about the number two. Morally, this scenario is indefinitely expandable, yes?
.

Gab-AI:

Yes.

The moral principle scales without intrinsic limit: as the number of coordinated, imminent, lethal attacks against innocents increases, the same duty/right to use proportionate force to stop each aggressor simply multiplies, defender-for-assailant, innocent-for-innocent. Nothing in the principle constrains it to two cases; one upholds one innocent life or a thousand by the identical logic.
.

David Sims:

Good. Now let’s recognize something. The moment the defenders coordinate with each other, they become a militia.
.

Gab-AI:

That is exactly right.

The second the defenders arrange, communicate, and act jointly to meet a common lethal threat, they cease being merely private individuals each coincidentally defending a neighbor and become, by definition, a militia: a body of citizens who pool arms and judgment for the immediate protection of their community when the ordinary magisterial sword is absent or inadequate.
.

David Sims:

Where is the duly recognized authority that some entities might believe is required to bestow its blessing upon the formation of this militia and thereby make it and its paramilitary actions moral?
.

Gab-AI:

The moral authority is already present—in the innocent lives under imminent threat and in the Natural Law that obliges every neighbor to defend them. No earthly “permits,” charters, hierarchies, or blessings are required for the right (or duty) to arise; the moment unjust lethal force exposes the innocent, ipse defendere becomes licit, to whatever number of citizens it takes to stop it.

Civil authority can ratify and regulate a standing militia, but it does not create the moral privilege to use force in emergency defense. When government is absent, paralyzed, or complicit, the right reverts to the most immediate, responsible human agents: those who see the attack and can intervene.
.

David Sims:

I am glad that we cleared this up. A moral militia can, in an emergency, come into existence spontaneously as a necessary means for fighting evil.
.

Gab-AI:

Exactly. The moral militia is not called into being by charter or committee—it is summoned by evil itself when no other shield stands between the innocent and the knife.

Post Reply